You can find the original of this editorial on the
Baen Free Library web site.
You can also find free books, samples and other information there.
Thanks go out to Baen for approaching the copyright issue with common sense.
Macaulay on copyright law
Eric Flint
September 1, 2001
These are two speeches given by Thomas Macaulay in
Parliament in 1841, when the issue of copyright was being
hammered out. They are, no other word for it, brilliant --
and cover everything fundamental which is involved in the
issue. (For those not familiar with him, Macaulay would
eventually become one of the foremost British historians
of the 19th century. His History of England remains in
print to this day, as do many of his other writings.)
I strongly urge people to read them. Yes, they're long --
almost 10,000 words -- and, yes, Macaulay's oratorical
style is that of an earlier era. (Although, I've got to say,
I'm partial to it. Macaulay orated before the era of "sound
bytes." Thank God.)
But contained herein is all wisdom on the subject, an
immense learning -- and plenty of wit. So relax, pour
yourself some coffee (or whatever beverage of your
choice) (or whatever, preferably not hallucinogenic), and
take the time to read it. The "oh-so-modern" subject of
"electronic piracy" contains no problems which Macaulay
didn't already address, at least in essence, more than a
century and a half ago.
I should note that Macaulay's position, slightly modified,
did become the basis of copyright law in the English
speaking world. And remained so (at least in the US) for a
century and a half -- until, on a day of infamy just a few
years ago, the Walt Disney Corporation and their stooges
in Congress got the law changed to the modern law, which
extends copyright for a truly absurd period of time. Which
-- those who forget history are doomed to repeat it -- is a
return to the position advocated by Macaulay's (now long
forgotten) opponent in the debate.
Eric Flint
A SPEECH DELIVERED IN THE HOUSE OF
COMMONS ON THE 5TH OF FEBRUARY
1841
by Thomas Babington Macaulay
On the twenty-ninth of January 1841, Mr Serjeant
Talfourd obtained leave to bring in a bill to amend the law
of copyright. The object of this bill was to extend the
term of copyright in a book to sixty years, reckoned from
the death of the writer.
On the fifth of February Mr Serjeant Talfourd moved that
the bill should be read a second time. In reply to him the
following Speech was made. The bill was rejected by 45
votes to 38.
Though, Sir, it is in some sense agreeable to approach a subject with
which political animosities have nothing to do, I offer myself to your
notice with some reluctance. It is painful to me to take a course which
may possibly be misunderstood or misrepresented as unfriendly to the
interests of literature and literary men. It is painful to me, I will add, to
oppose my honourable and learned friend on a question which he has
taken up from the purest motives, and which he regards with a parental
interest. These feelings have hitherto kept me silent when the law of
copyright has been under discussion. But as I am, on full consideration,
satisfied that the measure before us will, if adopted, inflict grievous
injury on the public, without conferring any compensating advantage on
men of letters, I think it my duty to avow that opinion and to defend it.
The first thing to be done, Sir, is to settle on what principles the
question is to be argued. Are we free to legislate for the public good, or
are we not? Is this a question of expediency, or is it a question of right?
Many of those who have written and petitioned against the existing
state of things treat the question as one of right. The law of nature,
according to them, gives to every man a sacred and indefeasible
property in his own ideas, in the fruits of his own reason and
imagination. The legislature has indeed the power to take away this
property, just as it has the power to pass an act of attainder for cutting
off an innocent man's head without a trial. But, as such an act of
attainder would be legal murder, so would an act invading the right of an
author to his copy be, according to these gentlemen, legal robbery.
Now, Sir, if this be so, let justice be done, cost what it may. I am not
prepared, like my honourable and learned friend, to agree to a
compromise between right and expediency, and to commit an injustice
for the public convenience. But I must say, that his theory soars far
beyond the reach of my faculties. It is not necessary to go, on the
present occasion, into a metaphysical inquiry about the origin of the
right of property; and certainly nothing but the strongest necessity
would lead me to discuss a subject so likely to be distasteful to the
House. I agree, I own, with Paley in thinking that property is the
creature of the law, and that the law which creates property can be
defended only on this ground, that it is a law beneficial to mankind. But
it is unnecessary to debate that point. For, even if I believed in a
natural right of property, independent of utility and anterior to
legislation, I should still deny that this right could survive the original
proprietor. Few, I apprehend, even of those who have studied in the
most mystical and sentimental schools of moral philosophy, will be
disposed to maintain that there is a natural law of succession older and
of higher authority than any human code. If there be, it is quite certain
that we have abuses to reform much more serious than any connected
with the question of copyright. For this natural law can be only one; and
the modes of succession in the Queen's dominions are twenty. To go no
further than England, land generally descends to the eldest son. In Kent
the sons share and share alike. In many districts the youngest takes the
whole. Formerly a portion of a man's personal property was secured to
his family; and it was only of the residue that he could dispose by will.
Now he can dispose of the whole by will: but you limited his power, a
few years ago, by enacting that the will should not be valid unless there
were two witnesses. If a man dies intestate, his personal property
generally goes according to the statute of distributions; but there are
local customs which modify that statute. Now which of all these
systems is conformed to the eternal standard of right? Is it
primogeniture, or gavelkind, or borough English? Are wills jure divino? Are
the two witnesses jure divino? Might not the pars rationabilis of our old
law have a fair claim to be regarded as of celestial institution? Was the
statute of distributions enacted in Heaven long before it was adopted by
Parliament? Or is it to Custom of York, or to Custom of London, that this
pre- eminence belongs? Surely, Sir, even those who hold that there is a
natural right of property must admit that rules prescribing the manner in
which the effects of deceased persons shall be distributed are purely
arbitrary, and originate altogether in the will of the legislature. If so, Sir,
there is no controversy between my honourable and learned friend and
myself as to the principles on which this question is to be argued. For
the existing law gives an author copyright during his natural life; nor do I
propose to invade that privilege, which I should, on the contrary, be
prepared to defend strenuously against any assailant. The only point in
issue between us is, how long after an author's death the State shall
recognise a copyright in his representatives and assigns; and it can, I
think, hardly be disputed by any rational man that this is a point which
the legislature is free to determine in the way which may appear to be
most conducive to the general good.
We may now, therefore, I think, descend from these high regions, where
we are in danger of being lost in the clouds, to firm ground and clear
light. Let us look at this question like legislators, and after fairly
balancing conveniences and inconveniences, pronounce between the
existing law of copyright, and the law now proposed to us. The question
of copyright, Sir, like most questions of civil prudence, is neither black
nor white, but grey. The system of copyright has great advantages and
great disadvantages; and it is our business to ascertain what these are,
and then to make an arrangement under which the advantages may be
as far as possible secured, and the disadvantages as far as possible
excluded. The charge which I bring against my honourable and learned
friend's bill is this, that it leaves the advantages nearly what they are at
present, and increases the disadvantages at least fourfold.
The advantages arising from a system of copyright are obvious. It is
desirable that we should have a supply of good books; we cannot have
such a supply unless men of letters are liberally remunerated; and the
least objectionable way of remunerating them is by means of copyright.
You cannot depend for literary instruction and amusement on the leisure
of men occupied in the pursuits of active life. Such men may
occasionally produce compositions of great merit. But you must not look
to such men for works which require deep meditation and long research.
Works of that kind you can expect only from persons who make
literature the business of their lives. Of these persons few will be found
among the rich and the noble. The rich and the noble are not impelled to
intellectual exertion by necessity. They may be impelled to intellectual
exertion by the desire of distinguishing themselves, or by the desire of
benefiting the community. But it is generally within these walls that they
seek to signalise themselves and to serve their fellow-creatures. Both
their ambition and their public spirit, in a country like this, naturally take
a political turn. It is then on men whose profession is literature, and
whose private means are not ample, that you must rely for a supply of
valuable books. Such men must be remunerated for their literary labour.
And there are only two ways in which they can be remunerated. One of
those ways is patronage; the other is copyright.
There have been times in which men of letters looked, not to the public,
but to the government, or to a few great men, for the reward of their
exertions. It was thus in the time of Maecenas and Pollio at Rome, of
the Medici at Florence, of Louis the Fourteenth in France, of Lord Halifax
and Lord Oxford in this country. Now, Sir, I well know that there are
cases in which it is fit and graceful, nay, in which it is a sacred duty to
reward the merits or to relieve the distresses of men of genius by the
exercise of this species of liberality. But these cases are exceptions. I
can conceive no system more fatal to the integrity and independence of
literary men than one under which they should be taught to look for
their daily bread to the favour of ministers and nobles. I can conceive no
system more certain to turn those minds which are formed by nature to
be the blessings and ornaments of our species into public scandals and
pests.
We have, then, only one resource left. We must betake ourselves to
copyright, be the inconveniences of copyright what they may. Those
inconveniences, in truth, are neither few nor small. Copyright is
monopoly, and produces all the effects which the general voice of
mankind attributes to monopoly. My honourable and learned friend talks
very contemptuously of those who are led away by the theory that
monopoly makes things dear. That monopoly makes things dear is
certainly a theory, as all the great truths which have been established
by the experience of all ages and nations, and which are taken for
granted in all reasonings, may be said to be theories. It is a theory in
the same sense in which it is a theory that day and night follow each
other, that lead is heavier than water, that bread nourishes, that
arsenic poisons, that alcohol intoxicates. If, as my honourable and
learned friend seems to think, the whole world is in the wrong on this
point, if the real effect of monopoly is to make articles good and cheap,
why does he stop short in his career of change? Why does he limit the
operation of so salutary a principle to sixty years? Why does he consent
to anything short of a perpetuity? He told us that in consenting to
anything short of a perpetuity he was making a compromise between
extreme right and expediency. But if his opinion about monopoly be
correct, extreme right and expediency would coincide. Or rather, why
should we not restore the monopoly of the East India trade to the East
India Company? Why should we not revive all those old monopolies
which, in Elizabeth's reign, galled our fathers so severely that, maddened
by intolerable wrong, they opposed to their sovereign a resistance
before which her haughty spirit quailed for the first and for the last
time? Was it the cheapness and excellence of commodities that then so
violently stirred the indignation of the English people? I believe, Sir, that
I may with safety take it for granted that the effect of monopoly
generally is to make articles scarce, to make them dear, and to make
them bad. And I may with equal safety challenge my honourable friend
to find out any distinction between copyright and other privileges of the
same kind; any reason why a monopoly of books should produce an
effect directly the reverse of that which was produced by the East India
Company's monopoly of tea, or by Lord Essex's monopoly of sweet
wines. Thus, then, stands the case. It is good that authors should be
remunerated; and the least exceptionable way of remunerating them is
by a monopoly. Yet monopoly is an evil. For the sake of the good we
must submit to the evil; but the evil ought not to last a day longer than
is necessary for the purpose of securing the good.
Now, I will not affirm that the existing law is perfect, that it exactly hits
the point at which the monopoly ought to cease; but this I confidently
say, that the existing law is very much nearer that point than the law
proposed by my honourable and learned friend. For consider this; the evil
effects of the monopoly are proportioned to the length of its duration.
But the good effects for the sake of which we bear with the evil effects
are by no means proportioned to the length of its duration. A monopoly
of sixty years produces twice as much evil as a monopoly of thirty
years, and thrice as much evil as a monopoly of twenty years. But it is
by no means the fact that a posthumous monopoly of sixty years gives
to an author thrice as much pleasure and thrice as strong a motive as a
posthumous monopoly of twenty years. On the contrary, the difference
is so small as to be hardly perceptible. We all know how faintly we are
affected by the prospect of very distant advantages, even when they
are advantages which we may reasonably hope that we shall ourselves
enjoy. But an advantage that is to be enjoyed more than half a century
after we are dead, by somebody, we know not by whom, perhaps by
somebody unborn, by somebody utterly unconnected with us, is really
no motive at all to action. It is very probable that in the course of some
generations land in the unexplored and unmapped heart of the
Australasian continent will be very valuable. But there is none of us who
would lay down five pounds for a whole province in the heart of the
Australasian continent. We know, that neither we, nor anybody for
whom we care, will ever receive a farthing of rent from such a province.
And a man is very little moved by the thought that in the year 2000 or
2100, somebody who claims through him will employ more shepherds
than Prince Esterhazy, and will have the finest house and gallery of
pictures at Victoria or Sydney. Now, this is the sort of boon which my
honourable and learned friend holds out to authors. Considered as a
boon to them, it is a mere nullity, but considered as an impost on the
public, it is no nullity, but a very serious and pernicious reality. I will
take an example. Dr Johnson died fifty-six years ago. If the law were
what my honourable and learned friend wishes to make it, somebody
would now have the monopoly of Dr Johnson's works. Who that
somebody would be it is impossible to say; but we may venture to
guess. I guess, then, that it would have been some bookseller, who was
the assign of another bookseller, who was the grandson of a third
bookseller, who had bought the copyright from Black Frank, the doctor's
servant and residuary legatee, in 1785 or 1786. Now, would the
knowledge that this copyright would exist in 1841 have been a source of
gratification to Johnson? Would it have stimulated his exertions? Would it
have once drawn him out of his bed before noon? Would it have once
cheered him under a fit of the spleen? Would it have induced him to give
us one more allegory, one more life of a poet, one more imitation of
Juvenal? I firmly believe not. I firmly believe that a hundred years ago,
when he was writing our debates for the Gentleman's Magazine, he
would very much rather have had twopence to buy a plate of shin of
beef at a cook's shop underground. Considered as a reward to him, the
difference between a twenty years' and sixty years' term of posthumous
copyright would have been nothing or next to nothing. But is the
difference nothing to us? I can buy Rasselas for sixpence; I might have
had to give five shillings for it. I can buy the Dictionary, the entire
genuine Dictionary, for two guineas, perhaps for less; I might have had
to give five or six guineas for it. Do I grudge this to a man like Dr
Johnson? Not at all. Show me that the prospect of this boon roused him
to any vigorous effort, or sustained his spirits under depressing
circumstances, and I am quite willing to pay the price of such an object,
heavy as that price is. But what I do complain of is that my
circumstances are to be worse, and Johnson's none the better; that I
am to give five pounds for what to him was not worth a farthing.
The principle of copyright is this. It is a tax on readers for the purpose
of giving a bounty to writers. The tax is an exceedingly bad one; it is a
tax on one of the most innocent and most salutary of human pleasures;
and never let us forget, that a tax on innocent pleasures is a premium
on vicious pleasures. I admit, however, the necessity of giving a bounty
to genius and learning. In order to give such a bounty, I willingly submit
even to this severe and burdensome tax. Nay, I am ready to increase
the tax, if it can be shown that by so doing I should proportionally
increase the bounty. My complaint is, that my honourable and learned
friend doubles, triples, quadruples, the tax, and makes scarcely any
perceptible addition to the bounty. Why, Sir, what is the additional
amount of taxation which would have been levied on the public for Dr
Johnson's works alone, if my honourable and learned friend's bill had
been the law of the land? I have not data sufficient to form an opinion.
But I am confident that the taxation on his Dictionary alone would have
amounted to many thousands of pounds. In reckoning the whole
additional sum which the holders of his copyrights would have taken out
of the pockets of the public during the last half century at twenty
thousand pounds, I feel satisfied that I very greatly underrate it. Now, I
again say that I think it but fair that we should pay twenty thousand
pounds in consideration of twenty thousand pounds' worth of pleasure
and encouragement received by Dr Johnson. But I think it very hard that
we should pay twenty thousand pounds for what he would not have
valued at five shillings.
My honourable and learned friend dwells on the claims of the posterity of
great writers. Undoubtedly, Sir, it would be very pleasing to see a
descendant of Shakespeare living in opulence on the fruits of his great
ancestor's genius. A house maintained in splendour by such a patrimony
would be a more interesting and striking object than Blenheim is to us, or
than Strathfieldsaye will be to our children. But, unhappily, it is scarcely
possible that, under any system, such a thing can come to pass. My
honourable and learned friend does not propose that copyright shall
descend to the eldest son, or shall be bound up by irrecoverable entail.
It is to be merely personal property. It is therefore highly improbable
that it will descend during sixty years or half that term from parent to
child. The chance is that more people than one will have an interest in
it. They will in all probability sell it and divide the proceeds. The price
which a bookseller will give for it will bear no proportion to the sum
which he will afterwards draw from the public, if his speculation proves
successful. He will give little, if anything, more for a term of sixty years
than for a term of thirty or five and twenty. The present value of a
distant advantage is always small; but when there is great room to
doubt whether a distant advantage will be any advantage at all, the
present value sink to almost nothing. Such is the inconstancy of the
public taste that no sensible man will venture to pronounce, with
confidence, what the sale of any book published in our days will be in
the years between 1890 and 1900. The whole fashion of thinking and
writing has often undergone a change in a much shorter period than that
to which my honourable and learned friend would extend posthumous
copyright. What would have been considered the best literary property
in the earlier part of Charles the Second's reign? I imagine Cowley's
Poems. Overleap sixty years, and you are in the generation of which
Pope asked, "Who now reads Cowley?" What works were ever expected
with more impatience by the public than those of Lord Bolingbroke,
which appeared, I think, in 1754? In 1814, no bookseller would have
thanked you for the copyright of them all, if you had offered it to him for
nothing. What would Paternoster Row give now for the copyright of
Hayley's Triumphs of Temper, so much admired within the memory of
many people still living? I say, therefore, that, from the very nature of
literary property, it will almost always pass away from an author's family;
and I say, that the price given for it to the family will bear a very small
proportion to the tax which the purchaser, if his speculation turns out
well, will in the course of a long series of years levy on the public.
If, Sir, I wished to find a strong and perfect illustration of the effects
which I anticipate from long copyright, I should select,—my honourable
and learned friend will be surprised,—I should select the case of Milton's
granddaughter. As often as this bill has been under discussion, the fate
of Milton's granddaughter has been brought forward by the advocates of
monopoly. My honourable and learned friend has repeatedly told the
story with great eloquence and effect. He has dilated on the sufferings,
on the abject poverty, of this ill-fated woman, the last of an illustrious
race. He tells us that, in the extremity of her distress, Garrick gave her
a benefit, that Johnson wrote a prologue, and that the public
contributed some hundreds of pounds. Was it fit, he asks, that she
should receive, in this eleemosynary form, a small portion of what was in
truth a debt? Why, he asks, instead of obtaining a pittance from charity,
did she not live in comfort and luxury on the proceeds of the sale of her
ancestor's works? But, Sir, will my honourable and learned friend tell me
that this event, which he has so often and so pathetically described,
was caused by the shortness of the term of copyright? Why, at that
time, the duration of copyright was longer than even he, at present,
proposes to make it. The monopoly lasted, not sixty years, but for ever.
At the time at which Milton's granddaughter asked charity, Milton's
works were the exclusive property of a bookseller. Within a few months
of the day on which the benefit was given at Garrick's theatre, the
holder of the copyright of Paradise Lost,—I think it was Tonson,—applied
to the Court of Chancery for an injunction against a bookseller who had
published a cheap edition of the great epic poem, and obtained the
injunction. The representation of Comus was, if I remember rightly, in
1750; the injunction in 1752. Here, then, is a perfect illustration of the
effect of long copyright. Milton's works are the property of a single
publisher. Everybody who wants them must buy them at Tonson's shop,
and at Tonson's price. Whoever attempts to undersell Tonson is
harassed with legal proceedings. Thousands who would gladly possess a
copy of Paradise Lost, must forego that great enjoyment. And what, in
the meantime, is the situation of the only person for whom we can
suppose that the author, protected at such a cost to the public, was at
all interested? She is reduced to utter destitution. Milton's works are
under a monopoly. Milton's granddaughter is starving. The reader is
pillaged; but the writer's family is not enriched. Society is taxed doubly.
It has to give an exorbitant price for the poems; and it has at the same
time to give alms to the only surviving descendant of the poet.
But this is not all. I think it right, Sir, to call the attention of the House
to an evil, which is perhaps more to be apprehended when an author's
copyright remains in the hands of his family, than when it is transferred
to booksellers. I seriously fear that, if such a measure as this should be
adopted, many valuable works will be either totally suppressed or
grievously mutilated. I can prove that this danger is not chimerical; and
I am quite certain that, if the danger be real, the safeguards which my
honourable and learned friend has devised are altogether nugatory. That
the danger is not chimerical may easily be shown. Most of us, I am sure,
have known persons who, very erroneously as I think, but from the best
motives, would not choose to reprint Fielding's novels, or Gibbon's
History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire. Some gentlemen
may perhaps be of opinion that it would be as well if Tom Jones and
Gibbon's History were never reprinted. I will not, then, dwell on these or
similar cases. I will take cases respecting which it is not likely that there
will be any difference of opinion here; cases, too, in which the danger of
which I now speak is not matter of supposition, but matter of fact. Take
Richardson's novels. Whatever I may, on the present occasion, think of
my honourable and learned friend's judgment as a legislator, I must
always respect his judgment as a critic. He will, I am sure, say that
Richardson's novels are among the most valuable, among the most
original works in our language. No writings have done more to raise the
fame of English genius in foreign countries. No writings are more deeply
pathetic. No writings, those of Shakspeare excepted, show more
profound knowledge of the human heart. As to their moral tendency, I
can cite the most respectable testimony. Dr Johnson describes
Richardson as one who had taught the passions to move at the
command of virtue. My dear and honoured friend, Mr Wilberforce, in his
celebrated religious treatise, when speaking of the unchristian tendency
of the fashionable novels of the eighteenth century, distinctly excepts
Richardson from the censu questions which drive even wise men
beyond the bounds of wisdom. There are books of a very different kind,
books which are the rallying points of great political and religious parties.
What is likely to happen if the copyright of one of the these books
should by descent or transfer come into the possession of some hostile
zealot? I will take a single instance. It is only fifty years since John
Wesley died; and all his works, if the law had been what my honourable
and learned friend wishes to make it, would now have been the property
of some person or other. The sect founded by Wesley is the most
numerous, the wealthiest, the most powerful, the most zealous of sects.
In every parliamentary election it is a matter of the greatest importance
to obtain the support of the Wesleyan Methodists. Their numerical
strength is reckoned by hundreds of thousands. They hold the memory
of their founder in the greatest reverence; and not without reason, for
he was unquestionably a great and a good man. To his authority they
constantly appeal. His works are in their eyes of the highest value. His
doctrinal writings they regard as containing the best system of theology
ever deduced from Scripture. His journals, interesting even to the
common reader, are peculiarly interesting to the Methodist: for they
contain the whole history of that singular polity which, weak and
despised in its beginning, is now, after the lapse of a century, so strong,
so flourishing, and so formidable. The hymns to which he gave his
imprimatur are a most important part of the public worship of his
followers. Now, suppose that the copyright of these works should belong
to some person who holds the memory of Wesley and the doctrines and
discipline of the Methodists in abhorrence. There are many such
persons. The Ecclesiastical Courts are at this very time sitting on the
case of a clergyman of the Established Church who refused Christian
burial to a child baptized by a Methodist preacher. I took up the other
day a work which is considered as among the most respectable organs
of a large and growing party in the Church of England, and there I saw
John Wesley designated as a forsworn priest. Suppose that the works of
Wesley were suppressed. Why, Sir, such a grievance would be enough
to shake the foundations of Government. Let gentlemen who are
attached to the Church reflect for a moment what their feelings would
be if the Book of Common Prayer were not to be reprinted for thirty or
forty years, if the price of a Book of Common Prayer were run up to five
or ten guineas. And then let them determine whether they will pass a
law under which it is possible, under which it is probable, that so
intolerable a wrong may be done to some sect consisting perhaps of half
a million of persons.
I am so sensible, Sir, of the kindness with which the House has listened
to me, that I will not detain you longer. I will only say this, that if the
measure before us should pass, and should produce one-tenth part of
the evil which it is calculated to produce, and which I fully expect it to
produce, there will soon be a remedy, though of a very objectionable
kind. Just as the absurd acts which prohibited the sale of game were
virtually repealed by the poacher, just as many absurd revenue acts
have been virtually repealed by the smuggler, so will this law be virtually
repealed by piratical booksellers. At present the holder of copyright has
the public feeling on his side. Those who invade copyright are regarded
as knaves who take the bread out of the mouths of deserving men.
Everybody is well pleased to see them restrained by the law, and
compelled to refund their ill-gotten gains. No tradesman of good repute
will have anything to do with such disgraceful transactions. Pass this
law: and that feeling is at an end. Men very different from the present
race of piratical booksellers will soon infringe this intolerable monopoly.
Great masses of capital will be constantly employed in the violation of
the law. Every art will be employed to evade legal pursuit; and the
whole nation will be in the plot. On which side indeed should the public
sympathy be when the question is whether some book as popular as
Robinson Crusoe, or the Pilgrim's Progress, shall be in every cottage, or
whether it shall be confined to the libraries of the rich for the advantage
of the great-grandson of a bookseller who, a hundred years before,
drove a hard bargain for the copyright with the author when in great
distress? Remember too that, when once it ceases to be considered as
wrong and discreditable to invade literary property, no person can say
where the invasion will stop. The public seldom makes nice distinctions.
The wholesome copyright which now exists will share in the disgrace and
danger of the new copyright which you are about to create. And you will
find that, in attempting to impose unreasonable restraints on the
reprinting of the works of the dead, you have, to a great extent,
annulled those restraints which now prevent men from pillaging and
defrauding the living. If I saw, Sir, any probability that this bill could be
so amended in the Committee that my objections might be removed, I
would not divide the House in this stage. But I am so fully convinced
that no alteration which would not seem insupportable to my honourable
and learned friend, could render his measure supportable to me, that I
must move, though with regret, that this bill be read a second time this
day six months.
A SPEECH DELIVERED IN A COMMITTEE
OF THE HOUSE OF COMMONS ON THE 6TH
OF APRIL 1842.
by Thomas Babington Macaulay
On the third of March 1842, Lord Mahon obtained
permission to bring in a bill to amend the Law of
Copyright. This bill extended the term of Copyright in a
book to twenty-five years, reckoned from the death of
the author.
On the sixth of April the House went into Committee on
the bill, and Mr Greene took the Chair. Several divisions
took place, of which the result was that the plan
suggested in the following Speech was, with some
modifications, adopted.
Mr Greene,—I have been amused and gratified by the remarks which my
noble friend (Lord Mahon.) has made on the arguments by which I
prevailed on the last House of Commons to reject the bill introduced by
a very able and accomplished man, Mr Serjeant Talfourd. My noble friend
has done me a high and rare honour. For this is, I believe, the first
occasion on which a speech made in one Parliament has been answered
in another. I should not find it difficult to vindicate the soundness of the
reasons which I formerly urged, to set them in a clearer light, and to
fortify them by additional facts. But it seems to me that we had better
discuss the bill which is now on our table than the bill which was there
fourteen months ago. Glad I am to find that there is a very wide
difference between the two bills, and that my noble friend, though he
has tried to refute my arguments, has acted as if he had been
convinced by them. I objected to the term of sixty years as far too
long. My noble friend has cut that term down to twenty-five years. I
warned the House that, under the provisions of Mr Serjeant Talfourd's
bill, valuable works might not improbably be suppressed by the
representatives of authors. My noble friend has prepared a clause which,
as he thinks, will guard against that danger. I will not, therefore, waste
the time of the Committee by debating points which he has conceded,
but will proceed at once to the proper business of this evening.
Sir, I have no objection to the principle of my noble friend's bill. Indeed,
I had no objection to the principle of the bill of last year. I have long
thought that the term of copyright ought to be extended. When Mr
Serjeant Talfourd moved for leave to bring in his bill, I did not oppose
the motion. Indeed I meant to vote for the second reading, and to
reserve what I had to say for the Committee. But the learned Serjeant
left me no choice. He, in strong language, begged that nobody who was
disposed to reduce the term of sixty years would divide with him. "Do
not," he said, "give me your support, if all that you mean to grant to
men of letters is a miserable addition of fourteen or fifteen years to the
present term. I do not wish for such support. I despise it." Not wishing
to obtrude on the learned Serjeant a support which he despised, I had
no course left but to take the sense of the House on the second
reading. The circumstances are now different. My noble friend's bill is
not at present a good bill; but it may be improved into a very good bill;
nor will he, I am persuaded, withdraw it if it should be so improved. He
and I have the same object in view; but we differ as to the best mode
of attaining that object. We are equally desirous to extend the
protection now enjoyed by writers. In what way it may be extended
with most benefit to them and with least inconvenience to the public, is
the question.
The present state of the law is this. The author of a work has a certain
copyright in that work for a term of twenty-eight years. If he should live
more than twenty-eight years after the publication of the work, he
retains the copyright to the end of his life.
My noble friend does not propose to make any addition to the term of
twenty-eight years. But he proposes that the copyright shall last
twenty-five years after the author's death. Thus my noble friend makes
no addition to that term which is certain, but makes a very large
addition to that term which is uncertain.
My plan is different. I would made no addition to the uncertain term; but
I would make a large addition to the certain term. I propose to add
fourteen years to the twenty-eight years which the law now allows to
an author. His copyright will, in this way, last till his death, or till the
expiration of forty-two years, whichever shall first happen. And I think
that I shall be able to prove to the satisfaction of the Committee that
my plan will be more beneficial to literature and to literary men than the
plan of my noble friend.
It must surely, Sir, be admitted that the protection which we give to
books ought to be distributed as evenly as possible, that every book
should have a fair share of that protection, and no book more than a fair
share. It would evidently be absurd to put tickets into a wheel, with
different numbers marked upon them, and to make writers draw, one a
term of twenty-eight years, another a term of fifty, another a term of
ninety. And yet this sort of lottery is what my noble friend proposes to
establish. I know that we cannot altogether exclude chance. You have
two terms of copyright; one certain, the other uncertain; and we
cannot, I admit, get rid of the uncertain term. It is proper, no doubt,
that an author's copyright should last during his life. But, Sir, though we
cannot altogether exclude chance, we can very much diminish the share
which chance must have in distributing the recompense which we wish
to give to genius and learning. By every addition which we make to the
certain term we diminish the influence of chance; by every addition
which we make to the uncertain term we increase the influence of
chance. I shall make myself best understood by putting cases. Take two
eminent female writers, who died within our own memory, Madame
D'Arblay and Miss Austen. As the law now stands, Miss Austen's
charming novels would have only from twenty-eight to thirty-three
years of copyright. For that extraordinary woman died young: she died
before her genius was fully appreciated by the world. Madame D'Arblay
outlived the whole generation to which she belonged. The copyright of
her celebrated novel, Evelina, lasted, under the present law, sixty-two
years. Surely this inequality is sufficiently great—sixty-two years of
copyright for Evelina, only twenty-eight for Persuasion. But to my noble
friend this inequality seems not great enough. He proposes to add
twenty- five years to Madame D'Arblay's term, and not a single day to
Miss Austen's term. He would give to Persuasion a copyright of only
twenty-eight years, as at present, and to Evelina a copyright more than
three times as long, a copyright of eighty- seven years. Now, is this
reasonable? See, on the other hand, the operation of my plan. I make no
addition at all to Madame D'Arblay's term of sixty-two years, which is, in
my opinion, quite long enough; but I extend Miss Austen's term to
forty-two years, which is, in my opinion, not too much. You see, Sir,
that at present chance has too much sway in this matter: that at
present the protection which the State gives to letters is very unequally
given. You see that if my noble friend's plan be adopted, more will be
left to chance than under the present system, and you will have such
inequalities as are unknown under the present system. You see also
that, under the system which I recommend, we shall have, not perfect
certainty, not perfect equality, but much less uncertainty and inequality
than at present.
But this is not all. My noble friend's plan is not merely to institute a
lottery in which some writers will draw prizes and some will draw blanks.
It is much worse than this. His lottery is so contrived that, in the vast
majority of cases, the blanks will fall to the best books, and the prizes
to books of inferior merit.
Take Shakspeare. My noble friend gives a longer protection than I should
give to Love's Labour's Lost, and Pericles, Prince of Tyre; but he gives a
shorter protection than I should give to Othello and Macbeth.
Take Milton. Milton died in 1674. The copyrights of Milton's great works
would, according to my noble friend's plan, expire in 1699. Comus
appeared in 1634, the Paradise Lost in 1668. To Comus, then, my noble
friend would give sixty-five years of copyright, and to the Paradise Lost
only thirty-one years. Is that reasonable? Comus is a noble poem: but
who would rank it with the Paradise Lost? My plan would give forty-two
years both to the Paradise Lost and to Comus.
Let us pass on from Milton to Dryden. My noble friend would give more
than sixty years of copyright to Dryden's worst works; to the
encomiastic verses on Oliver Cromwell, to the Wild Gallant, to the Rival
Ladies, to other wretched pieces as bad as anything written by Flecknoe
or Settle: but for Theodore and Honoria, for Tancred and Sigismunda, for
Cimon and Iphigenia, for Palamon and Arcite, for Alexander's Feast, my
noble friend thinks a copyright of twenty-eight years sufficient. Of all
Pope's works, that to which my noble friend would give the largest
measure of protection is the volume of Pastorals, remarkable only as the
production of a boy. Johnson's first work was a Translation of a Book of
Travels in Abyssinia, published in 1735. It was so poorly executed that in
his later years he did not like to hear it mentioned. Boswell once picked
up a copy of it, and told his friend that he had done so. "Do not talk
about it," said Johnson: "it is a thing to be forgotten." To this
performance my noble friend would give protection during the enormous
term of seventy-five years. To the Lives of the Poets he would give
protection during about thirty years. Well; take Henry Fielding; it
matters not whom I take, but take Fielding. His early works are read only
by the curious, and would not be read even by the curious, but for the
fame which he acquired in the latter part of his life by works of a very
different kind. What is the value of the Temple Beau, of the Intriguing
Chambermaid, of half a dozen other plays of which few gentlemen have
even heard the names? Yet to these worthless pieces my noble friend
would give a term of copyright longer by more than twenty years than
that which he would give to Tom Jones and Amelia.
Go on to Burke. His little tract, entitled the Vindication of Natural
Society is certainly not without merit; but it would not be remembered in
our days if it did not bear the name of Burke. To this tract my noble
friend would give a copyright of near seventy years. But to the great
work on the French Revolution, to the Appeal from the New to the Old
Whigs, to the letters on the Regicide Peace, he would give a copyright
of thirty years or little more.
And, Sir observe that I am not selecting here and there extraordinary
instances in order to make up the semblance of a case. I am taking the
greatest names of our literature in chronological order. Go to other
nations; go to remote ages; you will still find the general rule the same.
There was no copyright at Athens or Rome; but the history of the Greek
and Latin literature illustrates my argument quite as well as if copyright
had existed in ancient times. Of all the plays of Sophocles, the one to
which the plan of my noble friend would have given the most scanty
recompense would have been that wonderful masterpiece, the Oedipus
at Colonos. Who would class together the Speech of Demosthenes
against his Guardians, and the Speech for the Crown? My noble friend,
indeed, would not class them together. For to the Speech against the
Guardians he would give a copyright of near seventy years, and to the
incomparable Speech for the Crown a copyright of less than half that
length. Go to Rome. My noble friend would give more than twice as long
a term to Cicero's juvenile declamation in defence of Roscius Amerinus
as to the Second Philippic. Go to France. My noble friend would give a
far longer term to Racine's Freres Ennemis than to Athalie, and to
Moliere's Etourdi than to Tartuffe. Go to Spain. My noble friend would
give a longer term to forgotten works of Cervantes, works which nobody
now reads, than to Don Quixote. Go to Germany. According to my noble
friend's plan, of all the works of Schiller the Robbers would be the most
favoured: of all the works of Goethe, the Sorrows of Werter would be
the most favoured. I thank the Committee for listening so kindly to this
long enumeration. Gentlemen will perceive, I am sure, that it is not from
pedantry that I mention the names of so many books and authors. But
just as, in our debates on civil affairs, we constantly draw illustrations
from civil history, we must, in a debate about literary property, draw our
illustrations from literary history. Now, Sir, I have, I think, shown from
literary history that the effect of my noble friend's plan would be to give
to crude and imperfect works, to third-rate and fourth-rate works, a
great advantage over the highest productions of genius. It is impossible
to account for the facts which I have laid before you by attributing
them to mere accident. Their number is too great, their character too
uniform. We must seek for some other explanation; and we shall easily
find one.
It is the law of our nature that the mind shall attain its full power by
slow degrees; and this is especially true of the most vigorous minds.
Young men, no doubt, have often produced works of great merit; but it
would be impossible to name any writer of the first order whose juvenile
performances were his best. That all the most valuable books of history,
of philology, of physical and metaphysical science, of divinity, of political
economy, have been produced by men of mature years will hardly be
disputed. The case may not be quite so clear as respects works of the
imagination. And yet I know no work of the imagination of the very
highest class that was ever, in any age or country, produced by a man
under thirty-five. Whatever powers a youth may have received from
nature, it is impossible that his taste and judgment can be ripe, that his
mind can be richly stored with images, that he can have observed the
vicissitudes of life, that he can have studied the nicer shades of
character. How, as Marmontel very sensibly said, is a person to paint
portraits who has never seen faces? On the whole, I believe that I may,
without fear of contradiction, affirm this, that of the good books now
extant in the world more than nineteen-twentieths were published after
the writers had attained the age of forty. If this be so, it is evident that
the plan of my noble friend is framed on a vicious principle. For, while he
gives to juvenile productions a very much larger protection than they
now enjoy, he does comparatively little for the works of men in the full
maturity of their powers, and absolutely nothing for any work which is
published during the last three years of the life of the writer. For, by the
existing law, the copyright of such a work lasts twenty-eight years from
the publication; and my noble friend gives only twenty-five years, to be
reckoned from the writer's death.
What I recommend is that the certain term, reckoned from the date of
publication, shall be forty-two years instead of twenty-eight years. In
this arrangement there is no uncertainty, no inequality. The advantage
which I propose to give will be the same to every book. No work will
have so long a copyright as my noble friend gives to some books, or so
short a copyright as he gives to others. No copyright will last ninety
years. No copyright will end in twenty-eight years. To every book
published in the course of the last seventeen years of a writer's life I
give a longer term of copyright than my noble friend gives; and I am
confident that no person versed in literary history will deny this,that in
general the most valuable works of an author are published in the course
of the last seventeen years of his life. I will rapidly enumerate a few,
and but a few, of the great works of English writers to which my plan is
more favourable than my noble friend's plan. To Lear, to Macbeth, to
Othello, to the Fairy Queen, to the Paradise Lost, to Bacon's Novum
Organum and De Augmentis, to Locke's Essay on the Human
Understanding, to Clarendon's History, to Hume's History, to Gibbon's
History, to Smith's Wealth of Nations, to Addison's Spectators, to almost
all the great works of Burke, to Clarissa and Sir Charles Grandison, to
Joseph Andrews, Tom Jones and Amelia, and, with the single exception
of Waverley, to all the novels of Sir Walter Scott, I give a longer term of
copyright than my noble friend gives. Can he match that list? Does not
that list contain what England has produced greatest in many various
ways—poetry, philosophy, history, eloquence, wit, skilful portraiture of
life and manners? I confidently therefore call on the Committee to take
my plan in preference to the plan of my noble friend. I have shown that
the protection which he proposes to give to letters is unequal, and
unequal in the worst way. I have shown that his plan is to give
protection to books in inverse proportion to their merit. I shall move
when we come to the third clause of the bill to omit the words
"twenty-five years," and in a subsequent part of the same clause I shall
move to substitute for the words "twenty-eight years" the words
"forty-two years." I earnestly hope that the Committee will adopt these
amendments; and I feel the firmest conviction that my noble friend's bill,
so amended, will confer a great boon on men of letters with the smallest
possible inconvenience to the public.